My
group’s approach to “Across Archives ‘n Ngrams” could be compared to a camera’s
focus options. While the purpose of the assignment was to consider patterns using our chosen terms (to zoom out and examine terms across texts and over time), we
honed in on the details of those terms. We focused carefully on the individual
instances and patterns presented in the archival tools themselves, noting the local inconsistencies and surprises they
revealed. We recognize that our close and deliberate analysis needed to take a big step backward.
To look at this:
In the larger scheme of this:
(what do those little orange locations tell us about the term in this text and in the others?)
To respond to Dr. Graban’s prompt, the
archival tools addressed and illumined my understanding of the texts. My post
will consider the use of perception and language, both as the basis for Locke’s
theory of understanding and as guiding terms for Campbell’s “The Philosophy of
Rhetoric.”
This week’s Book III excerpt of Locke’s “An Essay Concerning Human Understanding” focused primarily on language and the abstract nature of words. The concordance helped us to understand the role of larger concepts in Locke’s complete essay. For instance, perception was Locke’s most used term. Perception precedes language, serving as a kind of imperfect doorway to understanding. As Bizzell and Herzberg note, Locke’s pursuit of “truth in the physical world” led to his “attempts to understand knowledge as a psychological phenomenon” (814). The psychological concept of perception, taken up as philosophical inquiry during the Enlightenment period, is tied to the senses (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy); the senses perceive stimuli which, related to Locke’s essay, becomes translated into a series of signs (Bizzell and Herzberg 817). Therefore, as Locke reflects upon human understanding, which begins with perception, he segues into language. Although it may have seemed obvious, the concordance furthered my understanding of Locke’s philosophy and created a mental picture of where these terms existed in relation to one another.
In “The Philosophy of Rhetoric,” the Internet
Archive gave me a new perspective on Campbell’s text as an educational tool.
While Campbell continues to build on Locke’s philosophy, he also examines
rhetoric related to “elocution, grammar, pulpit oratory, and literary
criticisms” (Bizzell and Herzberg 898). The Internet Archive found “language”
was used on more occasions than the other terms. Building on Locke’s idea that
perception leads to language, Campbell frequently depicts language – the
highest form of which is eloquence – in a philosophical context and one related
to usage.
Although learning did not have a strong,
quantifiable presence in the archive, the few times it did turn up, there
seemed to be an implicit connection between understanding and education/study,
particularly within Campbell’s usage sections. For instance, our search results
tied language to Campbell’s “The Foundations and Essential Properties of
Elocutions,” a section which looks at the conventions of language and grammar
including style. Similarly, the instances where “writing” is used in Campbell’s
text linked the term to usage and occasion. In one of our passages, Campbell
notes tautology as an unnecessary ornament for “descriptive, pathetic, and
declamatory” writing (358). He critiques certain authors, providing specific examples
and explaining their errors in thought and presentation. In such places, I am
reminded that Bizzell and Herzberg excerpted the more philosophical sections of
Campbell’s text in order to draw clearer connections to authors such as Locke
and as a response to Hume's "famous attack on religion" (Bizzell and
Herzberg 898).
Certainly, our presentation materials
concentrated on the terms’ immediate contexts and the tools’ findings. That
said, perhaps these became our focus because Angela and I kept returning to a
discussion of what the tools were teaching us about research and making
meaning. Our approach reflects detailed, localized attempts to extract meaning
from the terms -- a meaning that an algorithm, a concordance, and an Ngram
cannot write out for us. As students and as researchers, we must draw
connections between terms which, taken at face value through the Alex
Concordance, could reveal very different results than if we were to look at
those terms in context. Similarly, the Google Ngram presented instances of the
terms over time, but if a term took on a different meaning from one century to
the next, the results were affected. There were so many tools and factors to
consider as we made (and continue to make) sense of our terms. Nevertheless, I
believe our approach to the project helped us better grasp the
reader's/researcher's role in making meaning of the terms, the texts, and the
larger conversations within rhetorical theory.
Works Cited:
Bizzell, Patricia and Bruce Herzberg. The Rhetorical
Tradition: Readings from Classical Times
to the
Present. Bedford/St.
Martin’s, 2002.
Campbell, George. The Philosophy of Rhetoric, Edited
by Lloyd F. Bitzer. 2nd ed., Southern
Illinois University Press, 1963. The
Internet Archive.
https://archive.org/details/philosophyofrhet00campuoft.
----. “The Philosophy of Rhetoric.” The Rhetorical
Tradition: Readings from Classical Times to
the Present, edited by Patricia Bizzell and Bruce Herzberg, Bedford/St.
Martin’s, 2002, pp. 902-946.
“John Locke.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
2001.
Locke, John. “From An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.” The
Rhetorical Tradition:
Readings from Classical Times to the Present, edited by Patricia Bizzell and Bruce Herzberg,
Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2002, pp. 817-827.
No comments:
Post a Comment